Добавил:
Опубликованный материал нарушает ваши авторские права? Сообщите нам.
Вуз: Предмет: Файл:

Экзамен зачет учебный год 2023 / [Andreas_Fllesdal,_Birgit_Peters,_Geir_Ulfstein]-1

.pdf
Скачиваний:
1
Добавлен:
20.12.2022
Размер:
2.22 Mб
Скачать

the margin of appreciation doctrine

67

Belgian Linguistic case, concerning the right to education under article 2 of the First Protocol, as well as the principle of non-discrimination under article 14.20 The Court recognised the intrinsically subsidiary nature of its European supervision with respect to regulations of the system of education.21 Thereafter, the experimental spheres of the margin of appreciation were expanded to cover issues of the freedom of peaceful assembly and association under article 11, with specic regard to trade union activities.22

Subsequently, the concept of a margin of appreciation has been spread in a spectacular manner in relation to substantive rights provisions, in particular due process guarantees under articles 5623 and the personal freedomrights under articles 811,24 and two supplementary provisions of articles 13 and 14.25 The rationales for the dynamic evolution of this concept were most saliently spelt out in cases addressing the limitation clauses under articles 811 and article 1 of the First Protocol.

20The Commission emphasised that the rst sentence of art. 2 of the Protocol allows states a certain discretionwith regard to the measures to be taken to secure the enjoyment of the right guaranteed: ECommHR, Case relating to Certain Aspects of the Laws on the Use of Languages in Education in Belgium (Belgian Linguistic case) (Appl. Nos. 1474, 1677 and 1691/62), Report (Commission), 24 June 1965, Series B, Vol. 3, at 307, para. 401.

21The Court noted as follows:

The right to education guaranteed by the rst sentence of Article 2 of the Protocol by its very nature calls for regulation by the State, regulation which may vary in time and place according to the needs and resources of the community and of individuals. It goes without saying that such regulation must never injure the substance of the right to education nor conict with other rights enshrined in the Convention.

ECtHR, Belgian Linguistic case, para. 5. See also ibid., para. 10.

22The Strasbourg organs allowed the national authorities a free choice of meansto realise the interests of trade unions: ECtHR, Union of Belgian Police v. Belgium (Appl. No. 4464/ 70), Judgment (Plenary), 27 October 1975, Series A, Vol. 19, para. 39; ECtHR, Swedish Engine DriversUnion v. Sweden (Appl. No. 5614/72), Judgment (Chamber), 6 February 1976, Series A, Vol. 20, para. 40; and ECtHR, Schmidt and Dahlström v. Sweden (Appl. No. 5589/72), Judgment (Chamber), 6 February 1976, Series A, Vol. 21, para. 36.

23ECtHR, Engel and Others v. The Netherlands (Article 50) (Appl. Nos. 5100, 5101 and 5102/71; 5354 and 5370/72), Judgment (Plenary), 8 June 1976, Series A, Vol. 22, para. 72.

24The rst recourse to this concept was seen in ECtHR, De Wilde, Ooms and Versyp v. Belgium (Vagrancy case) (Appl. Nos. 2832, 2835 and 2899/66), Judgment (Plenary), 18 June 1971, Series A, Vol. 12, para. 93. See also ECtHR, Golder v. UK (Appl. No. 4451/70), Judgment (Plenary), 21 February 1975, Series A, Vol. 18, para. 45 (restrictions on the right to correspondence).

25As is well known, Protocol No. 12 has made art. 14 a stand-alone, substantive right for the states parties to this protocol.

68

yutaka arai-takahashi

Among them, the Courts famous dictum in the Handyside case has spelt out the deferential approach that endorsed the latitudes of national discretion in assessing the concept necessary in a democratic societyunder the limitation clause of article 10. More precisely, a national margin of appreciation was recognised in assessing whether there existed pressing social needthat would warrant interference for the alleged purpose of protecting public morals:

it is not possible to nd in the domestic law of the various Contracting States a uniform European conception of morals. The view taken by their respective laws of the requirements of morals varies from time to time and from place to place, especially in our era which is characterised by a rapid and far-reaching evolution of opinions on the subject. By reason of their direct and continuous contact with the vital forces of their countries, State authorities are in principle in a better position than the international judge to give an opinion on the exact content of these requirements as well as on the necessityof a restrictionor penaltyintended to meet them. The Court notes at this juncture that whilst the adjective necessary, within the meaning of Article 10 § 2, is not synonymous with indispensable[cf. in Articles 2 § 2 and 6 § 1, the words absolutely necessaryand strictly necessaryand, in Article 15 § 1, the phrase to the extent strictly required by the exigencies of the situation], neither has it the exibility of such expressions as admissible, ordinary[cf. Article 4 § 3], useful[cf. the French text of the rst paragraph of Article 1 of Protocol No. 1], reasonable[cf. Articles 5 § 3 and 6 § 1] or desirable. Nevertheless, it is for the national authorities to make the initial assessment of the reality of the pressing social need implied by the notion of necessityin this context. Consequently, Article 10 § 2 leaves to the Contracting States a margin of appreciation. This margin is given both to the domestic legislator [prescribed by law] and to the bodies, judicial

amongst others, that are called upon to interpret and apply the laws in force 26

With hindsight, the Handyside judgment has provided the prototype of marginanalysis not only in the context of the limitation clauses,27 but also in any other context. For that reason, it is only since that cause célèbre that it has become fairly justiable to consider a margin of appreciation as a doctrine.

26ECtHR, Handyside v. UK (Appl. No. 5493/72), Judgment (Plenary), 7 December 1976, Series A, Vol. 24, para. 48.

27These include not only the second paragraphs of arts. 811, but also the third paragraph of art. 2 of Protocol No. 4. A similar formula can be seen in respect of the right to property guaranteed in art. 1 of the First Protocol and art. 1 of Protocol No. 7.

the margin of appreciation doctrine

69

3. Analysing the circumstances in which the margin of appreciation may be invoked

3.1Overview

Analytically, the main contours of debates on the margin of appreciation take shape in ve processes: (i) the process of fact-nding and ascertainment of fact; (ii) the process of interpreting and applying national laws; (iii) the process of evaluating the conceptual parameters of a specic ECHR right and applying them in relation to a specic issue arising from a member states concrete (measure to implement) laws; (iv) the process of balancing between an individual persons right and a public interest ground, including the evaluation of the means to achieve the social ends sought after;28 and (v) weighing in balance two competing rights and freedoms. The second process is related to the question of interpretive disagreements over a specic human rights norm, the profound question that in turn gives rise to judicial discretion. The third process links the rst phase of empirical questions with the second phase of delineating the ambit of Convention rights. This process necessitates examining specic (measures of) national laws in the light of the autonomousstandards of the ECHR rights. The fourth and fth processes of balancing appear most frequently in the assessment of the limitation clauses appertaining to articles 811 ECHR and article 1 of the First Protocol.

3.2The process of fact-nding and ascertainment of fact

The rst pattern of the operation of the margin of appreciation is seen in relation to the discretion given to national or local authorities in ascertaining relevant facts because of their greater access to information and social forces at hand.29 Deference to national decisions is corroborated by the comparative advantage of local administrative authorities in fact-nding.30

28Shany, Toward a General Margin of Appreciation Doctrine, at 917, 935.

29Carozza, Subsidiarity, at 73; and Judge Dean Spielmann, Allowing the Right Margin the European Court of Human Rights and the National Margin of Appreciation Doctrine: Waiver or Subsidiarity of European Review?, CELS Working Paper Series, February 2012 (hereinafter Spielmann, Allowing the Right Margin), available at www.cels.law.cam.ac. uk, at 89. In essence, this is what Greer calls the implementation discretion: S. Greer, Constitutionalising Adjudication under the European Convention on Human Rights, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 23 (2003) 40533 (hereinafter Greer, Constitutionalising Adjudication), at 423.

30Shany, Toward a General Margin of Appreciation Doctrine, at 927.

70

yutaka arai-takahashi

In this respect, the Court has consistently held that it is not normally within the province of the European Court to substitute its own assessment of the facts for that of the domestic courts and as a general rule, it is for these courts to assess the evidence before them.31 The most salient examples would be the assessment of fact-intensive elements. These include a state of emergency that would authorise a member state to invoke the derogation clause under article 15, evidence for criminal convictions, and evaluativeconcepts susceptible of greater room for subjectivity,32 such as sexual propriety and obscenity.33 As a result, arguably the most lax form of review can be exhibited by the Court in those areas.34

Nevertheless, several caveats ought to be entered. Clearly, the assertion that this phase is altogether value-free or ideologically neutral or free35 is contestable. The manner in which empirical data are amassed with the reconstruction of past reality can be susceptible to subjective evaluations. Further, even in respect of such a process of gathering factual information, the Court reserves the right to second-guess the outcomes of national assessment.36

3.3 The process of evaluating national laws

Akin to the evaluation of questions of fact, the appraisal of domestic law is in principle considered to fall outside the scope of the Courts review. The consistent jurisprudence amply demonstrates that it is in the rst place for the national authorities, and in particular the courts of rst instance and appeal, to construe and apply the domestic law.37 This

31See, for instance, ECtHR, Klaas v. Germany (Appl. No. 15473/89), Judgment (Chamber), 22 September 1993, Series A, Vol. 269, para. 29.

32Compare this, however, with E. Voyiakis, International Law and the Objectivity of Value, Leiden Journal of International Law 22:1 (2009) 5178 (hereinafter Voyiakis, International Law).

33Compare, for instance, ECtHR, Müller and Others v. Switzerland (Appl. No. 10737/84), Judgment (Chamber), 24 May 1988, Series A, Vol. 133; and ECtHR, Vereinigung Bildender Künstler v. Austria (Appl. No. 68354/01), Judgment (First Section), 25 January 2007, not reported.

34See, for instance, ECtHR, Pla and Puncernau v. Andorra (Appl. No. 69498/01), Judgment (Fourth Section), 13 July 2004, Reports 2004-VIII, para. 46 (holding that the Courts review can intervene only when the national courtsassessment of the facts were manifestly unreasonable or arbitrary or blatantly inconsistent with the fundamental principles of the Convention).

35Shany, Toward a General Margin of Appreciation Doctrine, at 937.

36See Spielmann, Allowing the Right Margin, at 8.

37See, inter alia, ECtHR, Winterwerp v. The Netherlands (Appl. No. 6301/73), Judgment (Chamber), 24 October 1979, Series A, Vol. 33, at 20, para. 46; ECtHR, Iglesias Gil and

the margin of appreciation doctrine

71

process necessitates the evaluation of national policy choices in relation to socio-economic issues under article 1 of the First Protocol.38 The second phase can be integrated into the rst process of evaluating empirical data. As such, this phase is also amenable to a deferential approach. The Strasbourg Courts intervention tends to be conned to cases where national assessment is regarded as manifestly unreasonable or arbitrary,39 or manifestly without reasonable foundation.40

3.4 The process of evaluating the human rights norms in the ECHR

This phase essentially concerns the interpretation of the terms of ECHR rights and the determination of their meaning and scope. Human rights law, while providing deontological constraintsand pulling judicial decisions in the direction of optimising rights, does not prescribe their content and ambit exhaustively.41 Indeed, despite inexorable increase in normative instruments and monitoring mechanisms of international human rights law both at universal and regional levels, it remains the case that one of the most conspicuous weaknesses of the current human rights system is the lack of a thick normative content, that is, the question of indeterminacy of human rights concepts.42 Hence, there remains ineluctably a measure of interpretive latitudes for determining their scope and meaning, and for reconciling conicting liberties in case of clashes between them. In the ECHR context, where the normative ambit and meaning of a human rights norm is indenite, the Court is receptive to the deferential policy, on the ground that national authorities

AUI v. Spain (Appl. No. 56673/00), Judgment (Fourth Section), 29 April 2003, Reports 2003-V, para. 61; ECtHR, Slivenko v. Latvia (Appl. No. 48321/99), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 9 October 2003, Reports 2003-X, para. 105; and Pla and Puncernau v. Andorra, para. 46.

38

See, inter alia, ECtHR, James and Others v. United Kingdom (Appl. No. 8793/79),

 

Judgment (Plenary), 21 February 1986, Series A, Vol. 98, at 32, para. 46; ECtHR, Former

 

King of Greece and Others v. Greece (Appl. No. 25701/94), Judgment (Grand Chamber),

 

23 November 2000, Reports 2000-XII, para. 87; ECtHR, Zvolsky and Zvolska v. The Czech

 

Republic (Appl. No. 46129/99), Judgment (Second Section), 12 November 2002, Reports

 

2002-IX, para. 67 in ne; and ECtHR, Jahn and Others v. Germany (Appl. Nos. 46720/99,

 

72203 and 72552/01), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 30 June 2005, Reports 2005-VI,

39

para. 91.

40 Jahn and Others v. Germany, para. 91.

Pla and Puncernau v. Andorra, para. 46.

41G. Pavlakos, Constitutional Rights, Balancing and the Structure of Autonomy, Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24:1 (2011) 12954 (hereinafter Pavlakos, Constitutional Rights), at 132.

42Carozza, Subsidiarity, at 589, 62.

72

yutaka arai-takahashi

are better placed to ascertain concrete measures implementing the abstract Convention right in specic circumstances.43 The problem of ambiguity of some human rights norms remains unresolved, not least because of the absence of common social or moral orderin Europe that would serve as a metric for normative guidance.44

Human rights norms are often deliberately drafted in a general and ambiguous manner to accommodate multiple eventualities in the future.45 Such an open-ended norm encompasses: (i) an ill-dened or inherently ambiguous norm;46 and (ii) an intrinsically discretionconferring norm.47 Legal norms inherently entail what Waismann and Hart describe as an open texture.48 Hart explains that [w]hichever

43 In the context of minority rights protection, see P. Keller, Re-thinking Ethnic and Cultural Rights in Europe, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 (1998) 2959, at 523.

44 S. Wheatley, Minorities under the ECHR and the Construction of a Democratic Society”’, Public Law (2007) 77092 (hereinafter Wheatley, Minorities), at 789. The line of argument is redolent of the hermeneutic postulation that the pre-understanding of judges, which is shaped by the shared topoi of an ethical traditionserves to forge the exible connections between norms and states of affairson the basis of received, and historically corroborated principles: J. Habermas, Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996) (hereinafter Habermas, Between Facts), at 200.

45Shany, Toward a General Margin of Appreciation Doctrine, at 910. See ECtHR, Odièvre v. France (Appl. No. 42326/98), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 13 February 2003, Reports 2003-III, para. 40; ECtHR, Boso v. Italy (Appl. No. 50490/99), Decision (First Section), 5 September 2002, Reports 2002-VII; and ECtHR, Vo v. France (Appl. No. 53924/00), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 8 July 2004, Reports 2004-VIII, para. 82 (recognising that the issue of when the right to life begins comes within the margin of appreciation which the Court generally considers that states should enjoy in this sphere, notwithstanding an evolutive interpretation of the Convention).

46For instance, see the notion of protection of moralsunder art. 8(2) ECHR. For the discussions on the German public law doctrine on indenite norms (unbestimmte Begriffe), see Arai-Takahashi, Administrative Discretion in German Law.

47Shany calls this a result-oriented norm: Shany, Toward a General Margin of Appreciation Doctrine, at 917. When analysing the theory of the margin of appreciation in the general context of international law, Shany argues that special features of the resultoriented norms are that: (i) these norms are indifferent to the manner in which a desired legal end is attained, insofar as its attainment is guaranteed; (ii) state authorities are given discretion over choice of means and manner of implementing such norms; and (iii) the path to the desired social/public end is uncertain: ibid.

48H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 2nd edn (Oxford University Press, 1994) (hereinafter Hart, The Concept of Law), at 1278. Brian Bix explains that the term open texturederives from the idea of the same name proposed by Waismann, a colleague of Harts at Oxford: B. Bix, Questions in Legal Interpretation, in A. Marmor (ed.), Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995) 13754, at 138. See also B. Bix, Law, Language, and Legal Determinacy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), at 717.

the margin of appreciation doctrine

73

device is chosen for the communication of standards of behaviour, these, however smoothly they work over the great mass of ordinary cases, will, at some point where their application is in question, prove indeterminate; they will have what has been termed an open texture.49 In a different work, he refers to problems of the penumbraor a penumbra of uncertaintythat surround all legal rules, which make it hard to assert that the application of legal rules to specic cases is merely a matter of logical deduction or automation.50 Hart accepts that uncertainty and indeterminacy concerning the requirement of the law is inevitably susceptible to adjudicative discretion.51 In his view, if a legal norm lacks objectivecontent (namely, an objectively correct answer to what the norm requires), then judges are given a scope of discretion to determine the content of the norm on the basis of extralegal considerations, including moral and political values.52 Where moral norms lack objective

49Hart, The Concept of Law, at 1278, emphasis in the original.

50H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, Harvard Law Review 71 (1957) 593629 (hereinafter Hart, Positivism), at 6078. In cases where legal disputes raise a question of law concerning a rules open texture, uncertainties as to the form of behaviour required by them may break out in particular concrete cases: Hart, The Concept of Law, at 126.

51Hart observes that In every legal system a large and important eld is left open for the exercise of discretion by courts and other ofcials in rendering initially vague standards determinate, in resolving the uncertainties of statutes, or in developing and qualifying rules only broadly communicated by authoritative precedents: ibid., at 136.

In another work, he aptly observes that:

The point must be not merely that a judicial decision to be rational must be made in the light of some conception of what ought to be, but that the aims, the social policies and purposes to which judges should appeal if their decisions are to be rational, are themselves to be considered as part of the law in some suitably wide sense of lawwhich is held to be more illuminating than that used by the Utilitarians.

[]

instead of saying that the recurrence of penumbral questions shows us that legal rules are essentially incomplete, and that, when they fail to determine decisions, judges must legislate and so exercise a creative choice between alternatives, we shall say that the social policies which guide the judgeschoice are in a sense there for them to discover; the judges are only drawing outof the rule what is latentwithin it.

Hart, Positivism, at 612. However, he is careful in stating that to describe such judicial role of drawing outas judicial legislation is to obscure some essential continuity between the clear cases of the rules application and the penumbral decisions: ibid.

52 He argues that if it is an open question whether moral principles and values have objective standing, it must also be an open question whether soft positivistprovisions

74

yutaka arai-takahashi

standing, as they often do, then the only way, according to Hart, to give effect to a legal norm entailing moral language, is to construe it as guiding judges to exercise their law-making discretionin harmony with their best understanding of morality.53 In essence, receptiveness of such indenite or discretion-giving norms to a margin of appreciation can be explained by the difculty in evaluating the moral, political and other value-laden considerations underlying such norms.

3.5 The process of balancing individual personsrights and public interest grounds

Arguably, the application of a margin of appreciation is most discernible and tenacious in this phase of balancing. The national authorities may be given latitudes of discretion in ascertaining the means (types, suitability, proportionality, etc.) to attain social objectives in a particular factual circumstance.54 This corresponds to the process of what Greer55 terms structured balancingbetween a right and a public good, or of reconciling clashes between rights. Similarly, Letsas’ ‘substantive concept of the margin of appreciationdoctrine is set in motion to rationalise the relationship between rights of individual persons and the collective interests.56 It ought to be noted that the term margin of appreciationin this context might be redundant if the

purporting to include conformity with them among the tests for existing law can have that effect or instead, can only constitute directions to courts to make law in accordance with morality: Hart, The Concept of Law, at 2534. See also K.E. Himma, Inclusive Legal Positivism, in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford University Press, 2002) 12565, at 1456.

53Hart, The Concept of Law, at 253.

54Shany, Toward a General Margin of Appreciation Doctrine, at 917 and 935. In this phase, for instance, the proportionality of incriminating measure (penalty) may be assessed.

55S. Greer, ‘“Balancingand the European Court of Human Rights: A Contribution to the Habermas-Alexy Debate, Cambridge Law Journal 63 (2004) 41234, at 434.

56Letsas, Two Concepts of the Margin of Appreciation, at 709. Letsas distinguishes between the structuraland substantiveconcepts of the margin of appreciation. The structural concept refers to the limit of the review conducted by the Court and the scope of discretion given to the national authorities on the basis of the vertical relationship between the Court and the national authorities. On the other hand, Letsas contemplates that the substantive concept of the margin of appreciationadverts to interpretive discretion in the area of substantive moral issues, such as the appropriate balance to be struck between an individual persons right and the public interest as a whole: ibid., at 70532; and Letsas, A Theory of Interpretation, at 801, 8492.

the margin of appreciation doctrine

75

notion of a fair balancethat the Court has frequently invoked were more systematic and coherent.57

When weighing the rights of individual persons against public goods essential to the Conventions constitutionalorder, the Court ought to provide a considered judgment based on substantive moral arguments.58 As noted by some commentators,59 the variable margin as a means to adjust the intensity of its review has much to do with the Courts struggle to make a hard choice of political morality when it is grappling with a complex balance of values between community goals and individual personsrights.60 The propensity for a deferential approach is enhanced, where decisions entail complex policy or political issues that are closely bound up not merely with the demand of sovereignty, but with that of legitimacy of the national or local community.61 Alexy recognises that decision-makers enjoy structural discretionwhen assessing competing interests that are crudely of equal weight and where a single answer is unlikely to be inferred from a balancing appraisal.62

57Compare A. Mowbray, A Study of the Principle of Fair Balance in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights, Human Rights Law Review 10 (2010) 289317 (hereinafter Mowbray, A Study of the Principle of Fair Balance), at 289 (describing this notion as a principle).

58Letsas, Two Concepts of the Margin of Appreciation, at 709. In the Refah partisi case, the Court afrmed that [p]luralism and democracy are based on a compromise that requires various concessions by individuals or groups of individuals, who must sometimes agree to limit some of the freedoms they enjoy in order to guarantee greater stability of the country as a whole: ECtHR, Refah partisi (The Welfare Party) and Others v. Turkey (Appl. Nos. 41340, 41342 and 41343/98), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 13 February 2003, Reports 2003-II, para. 99.

59Mowbray, A Study of the Principle of Fair Balance, at 316. See also Carozza, Subsidiarity, at 73.

60The restrained review standard has been discerned in cases regarding town planning, social and economic policy issues (including the transition from a community system to a free-market economy), the manner of taking cultural property into public ownership: Sporrong and Lönnroth v. Sweden (Appl. Nos. 7151 and 7152/75), Judgment (Plenary), 23 September 1982, Series A, Vol. 52; Broniowski v. Poland (Appl. No. 31443/96),

Judgment (Grand Chamber), 22 June 2004, Reports 2004-V. Compare these with Kozacıoğlu v. Turkey (Appl. No. 2334/03), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 19 February 2009, para. 53 (conrming the general principle that Finding it natural that the margin of appreciation available to the legislature in implementing social and economic policies should be a wide one, the Court will respect the legislatures judgment as to what is in the public interestunless that judgment is manifestly without reasonable foundation; yet the Court nding a proportionate balance to be upset).

61Mowbray, A Study of the Principle of Fair Balance, at 316.

62R. Alexy, A Theory of Constitutional Rights (Oxford University Press, 2002) (hereinafter Alexy, A Theory of Constitutional Rights), at 41425. See also M. Kumm, Constitutional

76

yutaka arai-takahashi

With respect to non-derogable rights, there is no scope of balancing, with the width of a margin of appreciation shrinking to zero.63 Judge Spielmann of the ECtHR afrms that the margin of appreciation is virtually inexistent when it comes to the non-derogable rights(right to life, prohibition of torture, prohibition of slavery and forced labour, prohibition of retroactive legislation, the ne bis in idem rule).64 What is more, deontological critics, including Ronald Dworkin, who proposes individual personsrights as trumps,65 are averse to the idea of balancing with respect to all human rights, be they non-derogable or not. These critics may consider that all human rights are unsusceptible of balancing.66 After all, the central tenet of Dworkins thesis is to place emphasis on the singular nature of human rights.67 Along this line, other

Rights as Principles: On the Structure and Domain of Constitutional Justice’ – A Review Essay on A Theory of Constitutional Rights, International Journal of Constitutional Law

2:3 (2004) 57496 (hereinafter Kumm, Constitutional Rights as Principles), at 581 and 588. Finnis argues that in a hard case, the requirements of moral soundness and t in Ronald Dworkins theory of interpretation leave more than one answer that is morally and legally not wrong, allowing leeway of discretion to those that interpret laws: J. Finnis, Natural Law: The Classical Tradition, in Coleman and Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, 160, at 36. According to Dworkin,

hard casesare discernible in instances where reasonable lawyersdisagree and where no settled rule dictates a decision either way: R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977) (hereinafter Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously), at xiv and 83.

63For instance, in cases involving anticipatory form of torture, the Court has consistently treated as irrelevant the conduct of applicants at issue, including the claim that they are allegedly posing a threat to national security: see ECtHR, Chahal v. UK (Appl. No. 22414/ 93), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 15 November 1996, Reports 1996-V, para. 80; and ECtHR, Saadi v. Italy (Appl. No. 37201/06), Judgment (Grand Chamber), 28 February 2008, Reports 2008, para. 138.

64Spielmann, Allowing the Right Margin, at 11.

65R. Dworkin, Rights as Trumps, in J. Waldron (ed.), Theories of Rights (Oxford University Press, 1984) 15367. See also, M. Cohen-Eliya and I. Porat, The Hidden Foreign Law Debate in Heller: The Proportionality Approach in American Constitutional Law, San Diego Law Review 46:2 (2009) 367413, at 395 (arguing that American constitutional culture holds a more traditional view of rights as strong trumps or side constraints vis-à-vis government action, and that this is the result of the great suspicion with which both government and the judiciary are regarded).

66See also Rawlstheory based on priority of the right over the good: J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), at 173; and Kumm, Constitutional Rights as Principles, at 590 (considering that this strand of thought can ultimately trace its origin to Immanuel Kants theory premised on the ideas of dignity and autonomy as opposed to the collective interference of the good).

67See, for instance, R. Dworkin, Even Bigots and Holocaust Deniers Must Have Their Say, The Guardian, 14 February 2006 (concerning the highly controversial Danish cartoons lampooning the Prophet Mohamed).